MCG
  • About
  • PAINTINGS
    • Catskillstyle
    • Fragments 2005-2015
  • Haiku-inspired Poems
  • Aesthetics

Whistler's Mother: Famous Modern Art

5/12/2013

 
Some people think of James Whistler as a 'realist' painter. They call him this because many of his paintings look like 'things'. His paintings look 'real'. Whistler was a first-rate 19th century avant-garde Modernist who was as controversial in his time as our contemporaries Damien Hirst, Tracey Emin or the Chapman Brothers. 

James Abbot McNeill Whistler was
 attacked by peers and critics for his concepts, his artwork, his spectacle and his personality. He was a profoundly influential painter. His ideas for form and content became highly fashionable and they continue to influence our contemporary thought.
Picture
Arrangement in Grey and Black No.1, aka/ “Whistlers Mother”
Academics and classicists were angered by Whistler's  dismissal of the use of literary or intellectual ideas in painting. Whistler promoted the thought that painting is a purely visual language and does not need to be about anything in particular. Whistler (along with others such as Oscar Wilde and Théophile Gautier) was a proponent of the theory that Art exists for “art’s sake”. He likened the visualness of painting to lyric-free music and named many of his paintings after musical terms such as "harmony", "symphony", "arrangement" and "nocturne."

Kicked out of West Point, rebellious in manner, style, and dress and living with his mistress, Whistler provoked 
an early scandal with his 1861/62 painting Symphony in White, No. 1: The White Girl. This painting was exhibited in the 1863 Salon des Refusés where it attracted more controversy than even Monet's Le déjeuner sur l'herbe.. Simply observing it today, you'd hardly understand why. 

Whistlers historical coup de grâce is his 1871 painting titled Arrangement in Grey and Black No. 1,  commonly called "Whistler's Mother". This painting has become one of the most iconic paintings ever produced by an American-born painter. It's been called the Victorian Mona Lisa, but when it was first shown, it was nearly refused by committee and described as a cold, empty and incoherent portrait. Critics ravaged the painting, in particular the stark and unnatural depiction. It's minimal tonal scheme reflects a contemptuous disregard for sentiment and the conventional color arrangements popular in the Victorian era. Whistler would soon, along with his concepts and paintings, clash head-on with another Modern art theorist and moral crusader of the time named John Ruskin.

John Ruskin was a 19th century writer, critic and painter who unseated the Vasarian version for progress in art that had held court for the several preceding centuries. Ruskin wrote a series of volumes titled "Modern Painters" in which he offered a complex if sometimes self-contradicting philosophy of art. Ruskin argued that the highest goal for a Modern painter should be the essential observation and expression of Nature 'as-is'; to look into the very heart of Nature and to capture an impression of it's "specific character" as contemplated through the artist's own temperament. Then to represent that impression just-so without manipulating it through convention, formulaic device or prescribed artifice. This approach to art making favored by Ruskin was decidedly anti-Academic and anti-Classicist. Ruskin decided that the principles of Academic artifice and design were to be made subservient to Nature instead of the other way around. Ruskin reached backward in time for a greater aesthetic value. In other writing, his architectural treatise The Stones of Venice championed Gothic Architecture as of a superior sublime spiritual purity, "greatness" by it's "strange disquietitude", as compared to the 'Beautiful' of the Classical style of Architecture. A study of his theories regarding Typical Beauty and Vital Beauty illuminates the nuances of his worldview.

Ruskin's effort promoted interest in the Italian Primitive artists. He believed that while not as technically proficient as artists like Michelangelo, the efforts of many of the earlier primitives such as Giotto were more perfectly and authentically felt and executed compared to what was done by later artists. Ruskin argued that the art production of the High Renaissance and generally anything made post-Raphael was mostly corrupt, decadent and deceitful. The values Ruskin offered were widely embraced by Victorians and inspired the Arts and Crafts Movement, as well a group of English artists who would call themselves the "Pre-Raphaelite Brotherhood".

The painter that initially moved Ruskin to begin putting his critical philosophy into writing for the first volume of "Modern Painters" was J.M.W. Turner. Considered an icon today, Turner's paintings were not always well received by critics. Multiple paintings by Turner had come under fire. One painting exhibited in 1842 and called Snow Storm--Steam-Boat off a Harbour's Mouth... had been dismissed as "'soapsuds and whitewash". But Ruskin saw in Turners paintings the embodiment of his aesthetic theory, and he rose to Turner's defense. In the first volume of Modern Painters in 1843, John Ruskin praised 'Snow Storm--' as being "one of the very grandest statements of sea-motion, mist, and light, that has ever been put on canvas."

To these points, Ruskin and Whistler do not seem much at odds. Both rejected the rules and conceptual theory historically embraced by the Academics and Classicists. Below is the painting by Turner just mentioned, alongside a painting by Whistler called Nocturne in Black and Gold – The Falling Rocket. Click and enlarge these paintings. Do you notice any vast difference in form or content? How do they make you feel? Are they as much different forms as a Giotto compared to a Vermeer? 
Picture
Snow Storm - Steam-Boat off a Harbour's Mouth (exhibited 1842)
Picture
Nocturne in Black and Gold – The Falling Rocket (c. 1872-77)
Standing in the 21st century and looking at these two paintings in the rear-view mirror while thinking about terms like 'realism' or 'naturalism' or 'modernism' or 'abstract expressionism' it might be perplexing to understand what possible outrage moved Ruskin to say the following about Whistlers Nocturne in Black and Gold : 

"For Mr. Whistler’s own sake, no less than for the protection of the purchaser, Sir Coutts Lindsay ought not to have admitted works into the gallery in which the ill-educated conceit of the artist so nearly approached the aspect of willful imposture. I have seen, and heard, much of Cockney impudence before now; but never expected to hear a coxcomb ask two hundred guineas for flinging a pot of paint in the public’s face.”

This insult would result in a libel lawsuit being placed by Whistler against Ruskin. This article by Erin Landry "Whistler v. Ruskin: Morality in Art Versus Aesthetic Theory" details the event and it's cause. 

These two 19th century Modern art advocates battled in 1878 not so much over 'form' itself, but because of a deep divide in philosophical viewpoint. What remains today from each of those two viewpoints is a  hybrid proposition that some painters today who consider themselves "traditional" or "classical" argue for when they champion 21st century representational painting. But this hybrid thinking isn't wholly accurate when applied to an imagined homogeneous principle that never actually existed. Because a piece of artwork is representational vs. non-objective does not by default make it "traditional", and certainly not automatically "Academic" or "Classical", in any sense of those terms. 

At the heart of the aesthetic principle guiding John Ruskin is a deep tangle of religiosity and socialism reflecting a core belief that Nature as given to man from God cannot be improved upon in any further aspect by man. Therefore, an artist most moral pursuit is to capture the specific character and essence of any object found in Nature ("be it man, beast or flower") and communicate that character as perfectly as possible without alteration. For Ruskin, this was a moral issue, and he had spent his entire lifetime fighting for a Godly moral cause for art. Ruskin was one of the most influential writers on art of any time, a critical contributor who shaped the Victorian worldview on art, so inescapably shaping our own current perception. The lingering element of Ruskin's Victorian naturalist-moralizing that many painters still labor under is, to quote Ruskin, "Nature is painting for us, day after day, pictures of infinite beauty if only we have the eyes to see them.”

On the other hand, Whistler believed that: "To say to the painter that Nature is to be taken as she is, is to say to the player that he may sit on the piano." While Whistler stated that art should not require a literary or intellectual foundation, he did believe in the necessity of design and artifice to evoke emotion and convey imagination and artistic intention. He understood and employed device and convention to arrange and alter nature sufficiently to suit his artistic vision.  But the lingering element of James Whistler's thinking still alive and well in the 21st century which was a far greater threat to John Ruskin's values than the arrangement and forced servitude of nature, was Whistler's incontrovertible belief that art should serve no moral or social cause whatsoever beyond pure, unadulterated, aesthetic pleasure: “Art should be independent of all clap-trap – should stand alone, and appeal to the artistic sense of eye or ear, without confounding this with emotions entirely foreign to it, as devotion, pity, love, patriotism, and the like.”

Prior to the 19th century, neither of these two ideas existed as stand-alone philosophies in support of art production. As systems, they are 19th century inventions. Art holds a history of ideas, the history of ideas as represented through their forms. The imagination and intellect of the creator, as well as the society that molded that imagination and intellect, is reflected in an art form. No art is 'idea-less'. Even Whistlers concept that a painting should be considered only for the pleasurable visual experience of abstract color and form and no other reason, is a specific (and at one time radical), idea.  

Today, you will often encounter the argument that 20th century Modern and Contemporary art are the culprits that destroyed 'traditional' art. It's often said 20th century art is all about 'nihilism', or the abandonment and rejection of "tradition" or "craft" or "Goodness". Some mockingly refer to the 20th century as the "age of 'ism's'". Some believe it's all the fault of people like Marcel Duchamp or Clement Greenberg. But when one encounters this type of attitude, you may be dealing with someone with incomplete knowledge of art-historical production and theoretical practice stretching back to the Early Modern period. More accurately, the century experiencing the most fracture in theoretical art production since the Quattrocento and that first produced the first multiple art 'ism's' was the 19th century.

Beyond standard textbook fare such as "Impressionism" and "Realism", enough of these societal and artistic 'revolutions' occurred that the effect was to wholly unseat the four century reign of Academic Art production(c. 1500s–1900s). Much of this started long before the Armory Show, which was only a reflection of that change. The roots of Modern Art stretch back into the 18th century and earlier. A focus on the underlying causes of Romanticism and Naturalism developed strength in the early part of the 19th century, ultimately catalytic for the first art movements which were given names by observers. For one example of these events, consider the movement Les Arts Incohérents. That art movement took place five years before Marcel Duchamp was born.

The two theories championed by Whistler or Ruskin each opposed the thought that guided the production of painters from Giotto to Watteau, It opposed the thought of their own relative contemporaries such as Reynolds, David, Gérôme, or Ingres. Whistler and Ruskin contributed to the abandonment of long-held Academic and Classical art theory and design principles established during the Renaissance, Baroque and subsequent eras. Both Whistler and Ruskin believed in a Modern Art, and both campaigned vigorously for a Modern Art, and their disagreement was over what a Modern Art should actually represent.

Today we are witness to a revitalization of traditional atelier training occurring on an international level. Some proponents of this painting revival seek to support their efforts through public campaigns against the modern and contemporary art. However, when these painters campaign against Modern or Post-War Art to support the representational painting model they imagine aligns with historic Academic theory and practice, they often employ the Modern ideas of the 19th century. They proselytize using the arguments that led to the disintegration of the Academic practice they wish to defend. 

If you call yourself a 'traditional painter' or "classical realist", yet you believe that a painting should not have to be 'about' any literary concept or otherwise intellectual, then you are a devotee of the 19th century Modernism of James Whistler. If you believe that the epitome of representational art means capturing the essence of Nature as fervently, accurately and as essentially as possible, then you are a devotee of the 19th century Modernism of John Ruskin.

If you are a 21st painter who imagines that you are working today according to a long-valued philosophy of art aligned with Academic principles or Classical theory simply because you paint "stuff that looks like stuff", you are mistaken. If you believe that a painting must represent the essence of Nature as accurately as possible, you are pursuing a Modern idea. If you think that a painting need only be about aesthetic pleasure of color, form and harmony and that it doesn't matter what you paint as long as it evokes emotion, you are a Modern Artist.  If you work according to any of those concepts, regardless if your work is abstract or imitative or some combination, you're a contemporary Modern painter. Because these views are historically anti-Academic and anti-Classical. No matter what you call yourself, and whether you know it or not.

Verisimilitude and Other Lies

12/19/2012

0 Comments

 
Picture
Picture
The Conundrum of the Workshops 
by Rudyard Kipling

When the flush of a newborn sun fell first on Eden's green and gold,
Our father Adam sat under the Tree and scratched with a stick in the mold;
And the first rude sketch that the world had seen was joy to his mighty heart,
Till the Devil whispered behind the leaves: "It's pretty, but is it Art?"

Wherefore he called to his wife and fled to fashion his work anew--
The first of his race who cared a fig for the first, most dread review;
And he left his lore to the use of his sons—and that was a glorious gain
When the Devil chuckled: "Is it Art?" in the ear of the branded Cain.

They builded a tower to shiver the sky and wrench the stars apart,
Till the Devil grunted behind the bricks: "It's striking, but is it Art?"
The stone was dropped by the quarry-side, and the idle derrick swung,
While each man talked of the aims of art, and each in an alien tongue. 

They fought and they talked in the north and the south, they talked and they fought in the west,
Till the waters rose on the jabbering land, and the poor Red Clay had rest— 
Had rest till the dank blank-canvas dawn when the dove was preened to start,
And the Devil bubbled below the keel: "It's human, but is it Art?"

The tale is old as the Eden Tree—as new as the new-cut tooth--
For each man knows ere his lip-thatch grows he is master of Art and Truth;
And each man hears as the twilight nears, to the beat of his dying heart,
The Devil drum on the darkened pane: "You did it, but was it Art?"

We have learned to whittle the Eden Tree to the shape of a surplice-peg,
We have learned to bottle our parents twain in the yolk of an addled egg,
We know that the tail must wag the dog, as the horse is drawn by the cart;
But the Devil whoops, as he whooped of old: "It's clever, but is it Art?"

When the flicker of London's sun falls faint on the club-room's green and gold,
The sons of Adam sit them down and scratch with their pens in the mold--
They scratch with their pens in the mold of their graves, and the ink and the anguish start
When the Devil mutters behind the leaves: "It's pretty, but is it art?"

Now, if we could win to the Eden Tree where the four great rivers flow,
And the wreath of Eve is red on the turf as she left it long ago,
And if we could come when the sentry slept, and softly scurry through,
By the favor of God we might know as much—as our father Adam knew.
0 Comments

Flemish Primitive Mystery Painting: Petrus Christus

2/11/2012

 


​The Mystery Begins.

Eyes in copy of the painting
In the early 2000's, I acquired a painting from a dealer in the Netherlands. As a painter, I'm able to decorate my own walls. When I acquire art, it's because something catches my attention in an unusually stubborn way. It becomes something I must have. This was such a painting, and a slice of it can be seen above. It's a portrait. 

Before purchasing, I inquired about provenance, age, etc.  Information was small, so was the price. When the painting arrived I was surprised by it's features. The construction is Flemish technique, which is part of it's charm. I assumed because of the subject and a few passages in the painting that it had been made as a copy from a museum piece. When the painting arrived, the crafting was of higher quality than I originally guessed. 

The painting was executed with perfect glazes and light scumbling over a soft pink ground. The ground shows through in various spots and was utilized in expert fashion to create the vibrant jewel like effect prominent in Flemish painting. There appears no over-painting nor restoration. The painting has a web of what looks to be authentic craquelure. 

While the cradle attached to the back of the panel is newer wood, the panel itself is older. The panel is cut with beveled edges and has a dark golden glow. The front surface is uneven. The grain, corners, and nicks and gouges on the back have been worn smooth and hard with time and handling. It seems to be made of oak and measures approximately 9.5 x 7.75 inches.

There is a certain feeling I have about the painting. There is a "weight" to it in my hands. A perfection of form. The late Thomas Hoving, former Director of the Metropolitan Museum of Art and author of the book "False Impressions"(1996, Simon and Schuster), describes the feeling this way: 
"The fakebusters I know all describe a mental rush, a flurry of visual facts flooding their minds when looking at a work of art. One fakebuster described the experience as if his eyes and senses were a flock of hummingbirds popping in and out of dozens of way stations." He describes this gut reaction, this immersed connoisseurship, as a key ability to determine a fake from an original work of art. This is clearly a copy of a famous painting, but for several reasons, I began to wonder about the impetus for this copies production, and from what specific source material it was actually made,

I'm not an expert on Early Netherlandish art. I do have a general understanding of the time and it's contributions, a few of the works, and a few of it's stars such as van Eyck and Memling. My knowledge lies more with Baroque and 20th Century painters, but I do know paint. I know line, value, color, form and a multitude of techniques for paint application. I've seen a lot of clunky copies, but this painting has unity, a delicate surety in execution. This fact and the craquelure make me wonder when this painting was actually made, and why it was made.

Most of all, because this is a copy of a famous painting  ... I wonder why the very specific element that makes it famous, was changed!

The Mystery Escalates.

The original version of this painting "Portrait of a Young Girl' was painted by Petrus Christus sometime around 1470. It is oil on oak panel, approximately 11.4 x 8.9 in, so slightly larger than my copy. At this moment, it's hanging in Berlin in the Gemäldegalerie. This is a photo of the original painting:
Picture
This is a photo of the copy in my collection:
Picture
_
Petrus Christus is known for his unique methods of spatial construction including corner-space devices, and being a first painter in the North to use a rational single point perspective. It was an older artistic convention when constructing a portrait to often place a sill between the sitter and the viewer, dividing that space. This painting 'Portrait of a Young Girl' is famous because it is considered the first painting made in which the sitter has been placed into a concrete physical space in our immediate proximity. Petrus Christus accomplished this by placing the girl into a room, and removing the sill which would separate us. If this element contributes to the unique character of this painting, why would the artist that made my copy of this painting put the sill back between us and the sitter? This is the equivalent of copying the 'Mona Lisa', but giving her a frown. What is the point?

The copy(in front of me now as I type this) does not seem like student work. Nor was it rushed. It is finely and delicately constructed. The drawing matches the original too precisely to have been sight-sized at some distance from the original. This copy was likely was made from an underdrawing that precisely matched the original. An engraving? Etching? A drawing from some book? The provenance of the original painting is fairly direct, recorded first in the Medici collection in 1492, and entering the Prussian royal collection via Edward Solly in 1821. Below are more detailed images of the painting.

Detail of Petrus Christus painting copy.

Cesar Santos and Syncretism

10/27/2011

 
Picture
Art transcends form. Great Art transcends form greatly. If “significant form” indeed exists perhaps it exists as a perfect essence through which Art reveals itself when informed intent is conveyed perfectly through skilled expression. The “skilled” part found not only in technique, but in the perfect realization of all choices that move toward the desired and finally expressed concept.

Cesar Santos creates images that at once delight the visual mind as they give form to vibrant questions. Are these images an insult hurled at modern and contemporary art by a master of traditional painting technique? Are they a painter’s biting inside joke? Or, are they perhaps secret homage to the imaginings and explorations of the 20th century? Do these images, through inclusion, further immortalize the work of the 20th Century artists that many figurative painters in 2011 wish had never been made at all?

Considered inspection of his body of work reveals that no branded artist labeled “traditional” or “modern” is spared conscription into Cesar’s world. From Rembrandt to Calder, Velazquez to Bacon, Santos conjures the imagery of these iconic personalities and casts them as 21st century celebrities in his own showpieces. Not merely a realist transcription of nature, these pieces tantalize as complex and compelling narratives, pulling you into this painter’s story and the questions he is asking himself and us.   

For centuries philosophy has exerted profound influence on visual art. Art and Artifice is inextricably tied to the production of meaning. In the early/mid 20th century, some philosophers explored the mutability of meaning, the limitations of linguistics, and the empty illusions of mass culture. The French philosophers of the mid/late 20th century such as Baudrillard, Lyotard and Deleuze, in extension of such ideas, explored thinking and concepts that still echo and influence today's 21st century art scene as they are even now being digested and understood. Sometimes it is said that within this current art scene "nihilism" abounds, and irony rules the day. Some believe that modernist and post-modernist philosophers sought to prove there is no real meaning, no real truth. Perhaps, but if 20th century philosophers showed that there is no real consistent meaning or truth because context changes, then they also showed that though the content of meaning changes and shifts, the container, the essence, the ideal form of meaning itself always continues to exist, in one form or another. That in itself seems a consistent truth. 

One important element postmodern philosophy explores is "difference as a means of production”, and is an idea appearing in the writings of Giles Deleuze. This concept suggests that “difference” is not a means of negation, but a productive mechanism unto itself. In his Difference and Repetition (1968, English 1984) Deleuze critiques our faculty of representation. As noted art theorist Robert Williams explains Deleuze thinking, "The emphasis that representation puts upon the principles of identity, resemblance, opposition and analogy works to suppress the real role of repetition and difference in the subjective constitution of reality. For Deleuze, difference is the basic condition of being, and repetition is an effect of it's 'productive power.'" Unlike the “Hegelian Dialectic” that requires two different forces to be in opposition, Deleuze sees that any two combining forces merely need be “different”, and opposition is not a requirement for a new meaning, or reality, to be born. This idea is not unlike the more ancient concept of "Syncretism" that is the blending of two or more belief systems, cultures or religions to form a new synthesized reality. These discrete elements need not be in opposition, merely different. 

Irrespective of Cesar Santos specific intent for each painting and whether or not his sensibility fully acquiesces to the syncretistic position his current efforts hold, it is clear he is an artist who embodies the most relevant avant-garde state of the continuum of visual art. A student of modern and contemporary art for almost eight years, as well as a student of the grand masters and classical painting technique in Florence Italy, Santos cannot help but be a product of his experiences and passions. From his visual mind, all he has absorbed and considered about visual artistic culture is brought to us through his brush, for our consideration. 

Alone, the exquisite poetry and craftsmanship of these paintings may guarantee their position as timeless art able to survive the coming centuries. Equally important, as a specific reflective snapshot of the broad artistic synthesis currently underway that is uniquely and immediately relevant to this early 21st Century, these images will most surely be considered as important works and assure their valued inspection for generations to come.

M.C. Guilmet
New Mexico
October, 2011

"Art does not imitate at all, because it repeats." - Giles Deleuze

On Seeing: When is a cow, not a cow? Molyneux's Problem Solved

7/19/2011

0 Comments

 
 
When is a cow, not a cow? When one has never learned through visual perception, what a cow 'is'.

Almost from birth, a human being starts to acquire visual information and process that information into abstract concepts of people, places, things, situations. Roughly one-third of our brain is dedicated to acquiring knowledge through visual perception; it's the most efficient manner through which knowledge is acquired.

There are approximately 30 different cortical areas of our brain that handle a different aspect of visual processing such as "line" or "color" or "movement". The visual brain continually acquires information, discarding some, searching for constancy, retaining essential information and comparing it to stored 'records' of all prior knowledge obtained. Plato theorized that particulars were formed from ideals.

We  now understand our brains work in opposite: ideal concepts are abstracted from particulars.
 
Consider for a moment the cow in the upper right corner. If a human being is born blind and stays blind, they will never understand the reality of what a cow is in the same way that a seeing person understands that cow-reality. Assume this person blind from birth is now 10 years of age, and their sight is suddenly restored. What will they see when they look at this cow upon gaining their vision?

They will not see a cow. Only patchwork shapes. They will have no knowledge of what the shapes are, as there is absolutely no concept or 'meaning' for a cow for them through visual perception. The same for a real cow standing out in a field. The cow and everything in the field will appear as so many lines splotches and blobs. There is no innate common knowledge of a cow. In human knowledge, a cow does not exist outside a human brain's acquired knowledge of it.

The form and meaning of a 'cow' is learned in our brain. The "essence" of a cow is acquired. In 2011 it is a neurobiological doctrine that ideal forms do not exist without a brain. Not cows, not cubes, not spheres, not triangles. "So what?", you may ask. The fact I can, in 2011, state this conclusion reflects a new understanding for an important and long argued philosophical question about the nature of human knowledge, therefore "truth" and "meaning". 


In 1688, the philosopher John Locke received a letter from one William Molyneux, a scientist and politician, in which a question was put to Locke regarding a very specific problem. Prior to the 21st century, this question was an open riddle whose outcome carried the conclusion for one or the other of two opposing views of epistemology. This question caused much debate through the years. 

William Molyneux's wife became blind not long after they were married. His scientific work involved optics, and he wrote a treatise on optics and the psychology of vision called Dioptrica Nova (New optics) (1692). A few problems in optics at the time surrounded reconciling theories about light and actual perception. Optics showed the inversion of the retinal image, but we perceive it right side up, why? The retinal image is flat, but we perceive distance and depth, why? Problems like that. Earlier theories, such as with Descartes, had imagined that the answer to these problems was some innate mechanism in which the ‘soul’ turns the image right side up, and that unconscious ‘natural geometry’ accounts for 'depth' perception. Apparently Molyneux was not satisfied with these Cartesian or Rationalist answers.

Likely while writing Dioptrica Nova, Molyneux read an essay by the philosopher John Locke, published in 1688 called “An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. In this essay Locke had theorized that someone who did not possess a particular sense could never in any way be familiar with the ideas, or realities, associated with that sense. Ideas acquired by a singular modality would not be the same as ideas acquired by multiple modalities. Color is one example. Without the sense of sight, a blind person would never be able to understand the idea or meaning of color, even with all other senses intact. 
Molyneux sent Locke a letter in which he asked:

“A Man, being born blind, and having a Globe and a Cube, nigh of the same bignes, Committed into his Hands, and being taught or Told, which is Called the Globe, and which the Cube, so as easily to distinguish them by his Touch or Feeling; Then both being taken from Him, and Laid on a Table, Let us Suppose his Sight Restored to Him; Whether he Could, by his Sight, and before he touch them, know which is the Globe and which the Cube? Or Whether he Could know by his Sight, before he stretch'd out his Hand, whether he Could not Reach them, tho they were Removed 20 or 1000 feet from Him?”

Simply put, the question posed to Locke asked that if a person who had been born blind and had learned to distinguish physical form such as cubes and spheres only by touch and name, were suddenly to regain their eyesight and SEE, would they be able to immediately recognize these familiar objects and distinguish these objects by sight alone? The answer to this problem carries tremendous weight.

John Locke was an Empiricist. In its extreme view, Empiricism believes that when you are born the brain is a “tabula rasa”, a blank slate. The empiricist takes a position there is no such thing as a common rational idea or intention that exists as innate human nature, and that all knowledge and understanding is primarily acquired through the senses.  Locke believed that we could not know the essence of things beyond the boundary of sense data, or the causal basis for the data we perceive. Locke offered that there is simple knowledge', that is knowledge acquired directly from experience in the world and knowledge that is simple is itself irreducible, such as the properties of “round”, “hard”, “and shiny”. 

Locke believed that all 'complex' knowledge was then constructed, or abstracted, from the particular concepts of simple knowledge into increasingly complex concepts of contingent particulars. Empiricists believe that any knowledge acquired is done so only through our senses and that experience acquired thus is the ultimate primary source of all concepts and knowledge. Any belief outside this as to causation, is 'super added'. Even belief in an expectation for causation(as in God) was theorized to be learned from experiential genesis.
 
“Herein therefore is founded the reality of our Knowledge concerning Substances, that all our complex Ideas of them must be such, and such only, as are made up of such simple ones, as have been discovered to co-exist in Nature. And our Ideas being thus true, though not, perhaps, very exact Copies, are yet the Subjects of real (as far as we have any) Knowledge of them.”
 
The predominately accepted theory of knowledge in Locke's time was Rationalism. There are a few flavors of Rationalism, but at the extreme polarized view to Empiricism, Rationalism supports the belief that knowledge is realized by means other than sensory experience. Rationalism believes that we are born with innate concepts and knowledge that are either part of our nature or given to us by God, and that sensory experience only realizes these innate truths, it does not provide them. If a cube and sphere are innate objective concepts independent of sensory learning and only realized by our senses, then a person should be able to tell the difference upon seeing them without learning them.
 
So you can imagine the impact an answer would have provided to the course of philosophy had Locke been able to produce an actual experiment with a human being to answer Molyneux. The predominant problem in realizing an actual answer to Molyneux's question was a lack of subjects. It's been estimated that in one thousand years less than twenty persons blind from birth have had their eyesight restored. 

Until now. (Scientists settle centuries-old debate on perception)

In 2003 MIT Professor Pawan Sinha initiated a program for children in India who suffered from curable congenital blindness. These patients, upon having their sight restored, could not immediately identify objects through the sense of vision. The forms these objects represented, did not exist to them.
Here is a video featuring Pawan Sinah explaining how our brains learn to see:
 
If it is not obvious by now, this discovery also speaks to the 'subjective' and 'objective' in Art.

On one end of the spectrum some people believe that all meaning derived from Art is subjective and there are no real meanings beyond subjective contextual interpretation, and so there is not 'truth' to art, only individual experiential meaning. On the other end of the spectrum some believe that Art represents or is derived from objective truth and meaning, and if there is truth, so there must be rules or principles associated with that objective truth.

New revelations from brain science studies have been creeping into the broader academic arena this last decade. A review of the American Society for Aesthetics articles will show various articles concerning brain science and aesthetics. Professor Pawan Sinha's work is only one example for how brain science will likely have a profound effect on the humanities and the teaching of art theory and aesthetics this coming century. While most artists I know seem pretty comfortable with their own current belief in the subjective/objective qualities of Art, it's possible that our understanding for what is subjective, and what is objective, might again be re-ordered.

So who wins, the viewpoint of Empiricism or the Rationalism? In practice, many philosophers take one or both of the positions depending on the issue discussed. Immanuel Kant in "Critique of Pure Reason" synthesized a position inclusive of both Empiricist and Rationalist ideas called Transcendental Idealism. It's been suggested that while theorizing about the 'mind' that Kant, and later Hegel, developed some conclusions that reflect how our brains actually work according to our current understanding of the brain. For instance, Kant surmised in his "Transcendental Aesthetic" that space and time are empirically real, and that we gain an understanding of objects through sensory input such as the visual observation of those objects in space and time; spatial, temporal, motion. The importance of these elements is observed in the above video as the subject is shown learning to 'see'.  

The 21st century Holy Grail quest is the pursuit for an understanding of consciousness. Many people are working together around the globe employed in this quest. A few weeks ago, I introduced the Charlie Rose Brain series. Below, you can view excerpts from episode two of the series, discussing visual perception. This round-table discussion features some of our most knowledgeable experts who are studying visual perception, Including Pawan Sinha.

 
0 Comments

"WHY do you paint?" | "WHY DO WE SEE?"

6/22/2011

8 Comments

 
Picture
Daumier, The Painter at His Easel, c. 1870-75, Sterling and Francine Clark Art Institute.
 
Ars Poetica    by Michael Hannon
Between heaven and earth I write one line.
Sometimes another line follows --
ambitious legions singing their way nowhere,
or ordinary messengers carried deeper into human life
by the music and its woman stepping out of her clothes
to the heartbeat of what comes next, 
What goes on for its own sake--
the page after the last page, on which we do not appear

 

"WHY do you paint?" An informal Facebook poll...

On June 6, 2011, I posted the above question on my Facebook wall and invited painters from different parts of the world to share their thoughts. One hundred and forty four painters posted an answer. I have never had the opportunity to ask this question simultaneously of so many painters in so many different locations and from so many diverse backgrounds. I have posted each and every answer here where you can read through and gain a sense for any core sentiment running through the thread. 

For privacy, I've removed the painters names, "likes", or other Facebook information. It seems this was a very personal question and some decided to answer by private message rather than in public. I did not share those private answers in this post, but many were of similar content to what the other painters shared.

Having this conversation with different painters through the years, a common theme seems to emerge that suggests a compelling 'urge' or 'search' of some kind that drives their effort. A need that must be met. This also seems to be an inward and self directed event more than an outwardly directed or altruistic effort, although those elements might contribute. Often referenced is a sense of 'timelessness', a 'zone', or some state of meditative bliss that is reached. We won't explore the 'timeless' nature of art making in this article as I have a great deal of information to share, but you can read something here related to this plasticity of time.
 

WHY ask this question?

For centuries, the 'Point of Art' has been debated and pulled like taffy in different directions. Some candidates for the purpose of art have included mimesis, idealism, naturalism, beauty, communication, expression, social commentary, cultural reflection, etc. Recently, Darwinism has been suggested. Philosophy, Theology, Psychology and the Sciences have all influenced how art is considered, valued, and produced. 

Thinking from people such as Plato, Aristotle, Plotinus, Aquinas, Kant, Hegel, Baudelaire, Fry, Bell, Beardsley, Greenberg, Derrida, Heidegger, Lyotard et al has had an impact on the Art World. Artists themselves such as Alberti, Vasari, Bellori, Le Brun, Reynolds, Whistler, Cox, Duchamp, Newman and others have contributed various points of view or theory. Religion, war, socioeconomic shifts, invention, discovery, politics and profits have all hammered away to shape how we think of art today. In 2011, the self-interest of the fractured, disparate groups from all genres, from all styles, are vying to be seen and heard and can make the conversation about 'What is Art' unwieldy. 

Yet, through all the nuanced debate or convoluted experimental directions one thing has remained constant: Art is made. Art Makers make art. And the consideration of art and it's assigned values all come after that fact. The consideration and valuation of art are "effect". Art Making is "cause". In circular fashion, the valuation and consideration do influence art making, but always and again, art making takes other directions. 

If the continuum of Art Making itself is the primary cause for the existence of the Art World, a singular question seems of most importance to me: what is the cause of Art Making itself?  This seems the likeliest place where the truest purpose and intent of art can be found, and in discovering those answers we might newly consider art and perhaps it's aesthetic valuation.

In order to keep transparent an attempt for the understanding of the cause of art making, it is necessary to divide the conversation and cull out the consideration and valuation influences of the Art Industry. For this approach, the non-maker's self-interest is better nullified from the discussion.

So in order to begin this exploration for the cause of Art Making itself, I reached out and asked Art Makers why they make art. Other people in other fields have been asking some related questions.
 

The 21st Century frontier; your brain.

Today in the early part of the 21st century, we have the benefit of some of the most exciting and enlightening discoveries that might actually begin to answer questions that philosophy, psychology and other fields have been seeking to answer for years. In the last few years, neuroscience has discovered more about the human brain than in all of human history combined. The importance of the discoveries being made about our emotional apparatus, visual perception, intelligence, creativity and so many other workings of our brain cannot be overemphasized.

The range of exploration and specialized focus on our brain is astonishing. Neuroscience, philosophy and psychology departments are undergoing a process of convergence in effort to discover answers about questions ranging from mental illness, drug addiction and disease to "what is consciousness?", and "how does the brain view art?". Philosophy and psychology have had historical impact on the Arts, but discoveries made in brain science may affect the Arts for the course of this century in ways not yet imagined.

When I talk with other artists, I'll sometimes hear facts quoted from old instruction books or art theoretical texts for which in 2011 we've acquired better information about. For example, a broader understanding of visual perception, it's mechanics and it's ultimate function, as well as a richer understanding of our emotional apparatus is available to us and can inform our artistic efforts. One approachable source for artists seeking to better understand some core mechanics behind their craft and that can also provide an overview and introduction to brain science is the Charlie Rose show. Charlie Rose has for some years now explored these topics in different episodes. Of particular value is the twelve part 'Brain Series..At the least, I recommend this first episode to better understand the immense overall impact brain science will likely have on visual art this century.

When brain science is introduced into conversation, there is often an immediate suspicion that an argument for pure subjectivity or a materialist/reductionist position will be introduced. I know that some of my friends reading this are people of strong religious faith and conviction, and who create from that position of faith. I don’t believe that any of the information I’ll share here poses a challenge to faith of any kind. God, or your personal concept of a Higher Power, can always seem to take one step back from these discoveries and if God remains the source for your understanding of these workings, there is not necessarily a conflict here. 

This information need not be viewed as a materialist/reductionist argument. There is a great deal unknown. It can be said that since the advent of quantum physics science has moved from a more deterministic outlook to one of 'probabilities'. The enormous amount of what we do not know seems to grow larger with every scientific discovery, the Hubble Deep Field Survey being one example. 

It is not incontrovertibly decided what parts of reality are ontologically objective or subjective.  Brain science can be said to be conducting an "epistemically objective search for what is ontologically objective or subjective." There are interesting developments, such as regarding emotion itself. While feeling states may be ontologically subjective, the emotional apparatus that all humans share and even share with animals, seems universal. As brain science is understanding 'components', some are suspected to be universal and 'hardwired' at birth, but how all these components work together is unknown; there is still no overall "theory of the brain". 

The hard problem of consciousness has not been unraveled. One influential philosopher who seems to be a materialist, but not a reductionist, makes the argument that consciousness itself is irreducible. Until the problem of consciousness is solved, and possibly even then, God remains as valid a possibility to the question of Meaning and Being as any other.

Still, we do not need all of the answers to these deep mysteries in order to acquire an updated understanding of the nature of visual perception and a possible 'Point of Art' best described to date. Many of the recent discoveries of brain science can already contribute to our considering an answer for our starting question "Why do you paint?".

Introducing the worlds first Professor of Neuroesthetics...

I am pleased to take this opportunity to introduce you to a special person you may not have heard of, Professor Semir Zeki. Professor Zeki is a professor of Neuroesthetics with the Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience at University College London. You may also never have heard of a 'Professor of Neuroesthetics'. This is because it is a new field of inquiry, the first of it's kind. Following is Professor Zeki's own Statement about the work he and his colleagues are conducting:
 

Statement on Neuroesthetics

What is art, why has it been such a conspicuous feature of all societies, and why do we value it so much? The subject has been discussed at length without any satisfactory conclusion. This is not surprising. Such discussions are usually conducted without any reference to the brain, through which all art is created, executed and appreciated. Art is a human activity and, like all human activities, including morality, law and religion, depends upon, and obeys, the laws of the brain. We are still far from knowing the neural basis of these laws, but spectacular advances in our knowledge of the visual brain allows us to make a beginning in studying the neural basis of visual art.

The first step in this enquiry is to define the function of the brain and that of art. Many functions can be ascribed to both. One overall function, common to both, makes the function of art an extension of the function of the brain: the acquisition of knowledge, an activity in which the brain is ceaselessly engaged. Such a definition naturally steeps us in a deeply philosophical world, of wanting to learn how we acquire knowledge, what formal contribution the brain makes to it, what limitations it imposes and what neural rules govern the acquisition of all knowledge. This catalogue is not much different from that outlined by Immanuel Kant in his monumental Critique of pure Reason, save that Kant spoke exclusively in terms of the mind. And since the problem of knowledge is a principal problem of philosophy, it should also not surprise us that the great philosophers, from Plato onwards, have devoted significant parts of their work to discussions of art, through which knowledge is gained and imparted.

Because knowledge has to be acquired in the face of constantly changing conditions, mutability is the cornerstone of the great philosophies of the West and East. But it is also the key problem for the brain in its quest for knowledge and for art, whose object, Tennessee Williams once said, was "to make eternal the desperately fleeting moment." Neural studies are increasingly addressing the question of how the brain achieves this remarkable feat. The characteristic of an efficient knowledge-acquiring system, faced with permanent change, is its capacity to abstract, to emphasize the general at the expense of the particular. Abstraction, which arguably is a characteristic of every one of the many different visual areas of the brain, frees the brain from enslavement to the particular and from the imperfections of the memory system. This remarkable capacity is reflected in art, for all art is abstraction. John Constable wrote that "the whole beauty and grandeur of Art consists... in being able to get above all singular forms, particularities of every kind [by making out] an abstract idea... more perfect than any one original." He could have been describing the functions of the brain, for the consequence of the abstractive process is the creation of concepts and ideals. The translation of these brain-formed ideals onto canvas constitutes art.

Art of course, belongs in the subjective world. Yet subjective differences in the creation and appreciation of art must be superimposed on a common neural organization that allows us to communicate about art and through art without the use of the spoken or written word. In his great requiem in marble at St. Peter's in Rome, Michelangelo invested the lifeless body of Christ with infinite feeling - of pathos, tenderness, and resignation. the feelings aroused by his Pietã are no doubt experienced in different ways, and in varying intensity, by different brains. But the inestimable value of variable subjective experiences should not distract from the fact that, in executing his work, Michelangelo instinctively understood the common visual and emotional organization and workings of the brain. That understanding allowed him to exploit our common visual organization and arouse shared experiences beyond the reach of words.

It is for this reason that the artist is in a sense, a neuroscientist, exploring the potentials and capacities of the brain, though with different tools. How such creations can arouse aesthetic experiences can only be fully understood in neural terms. Such an understanding is now well within our reach. The first step is to understand better the common organization of our visual and emotional brains, before we can even proceed to enquire into the determinants of neural variability. But there is little reason to doubt that a study of variability, of how a common visual activation can arouse disparate emotional states, will constitute the next giant step in experimental studies of the visual brain.

In such a study neuroscientists would do well to exploit what artists, who have explored the potentials and capacities of the visual brain with their own methods, have to tell us in their works. Because all art obeys the laws of the visual brain, it is not uncommon for art to reveal these laws to us, often surprising us with the visually unexpected. Paul Klee was right when he said, "Art does not represent the visual world, it makes things visible." We hope that the enormous international enthusiasm that a study of the neural basis of aesthetic experience has generated will prove an effective catalyst in encouraging the neural study of other human activities that may seem remote from the general discipline of neurobiology. It is only by understanding the neural laws that dictate human activity in all spheres - in law, morality, religion and even economics and politics, no less than in art - that we can ever hope to achieve a more proper understanding of the nature of man.

Semir Zeki

Some Answers?

Professor Zeki has graciously given me permission to share with you two papers that provide some insight to the questions that are the title to this post. The first paper is titled "Art and the Brain" in which the very important question is asked, "Why do we see at all?"
art_and_the_brain.pdf
File Size: 225 kb
File Type: pdf
Download File

The second paper is titled "Neural Concept Formation and Art: Dante, Michelangelo, Wagner"
neural_concept_formation_and_art.pdf
File Size: 110 kb
File Type: pdf
Download File

8 Comments

Unrequited

1/8/2011

1 Comment

 
I remember the coolness of the air conditioning on my neck, my collar damp from the late June heat when I entered her house. It was a fine new home suitable for what I’d heard she deserved. When I finally found her resting against a wall, I was not disappointed. Her warm solid weight and her cool delicate laughter enchanted me from first glance. I let my gaze wash over her, trying to take all of her in and hear what she was saying. Others with me drowned out the message, and soon I left.  

I did not see her again for half a decade, and when I did I enjoyed the good fortune to live less than a mile from where she dwelt. For several years she was my secret pleasure. I passed by her daily and would often stop to visit. Countless hours were given to her, feeling her presence, letting myself melt into her. When the great hall she liked to hang around in was very quiet, I could smell the salt of her breath, hear her faint whispers and moans, and see her maker’s presence in her skin. As ends come, this one came abruptly, now twenty years gone since. 

I saw her once more a little over a decade ago. It was a hurried, unsatisfying visit as time was short and another lover demanded my attention and led me by the hand away from her as I stole one more glance over my shoulder. I think about her now and then, what she meant to me, and the inspiration she gave. Sometimes I think, “I must see her one more time", but I never do. We both are not getting any younger. 

Perhaps I will this June.

Winslow Homer
United States, 1836 - 1910
Weatherbeaten, 1894
oil on canvas
28 1/2 x 48 3/8 inches
Portland Museum of Art, Bequest of Charles Shipman Payson, 1988.55.1
Picture
1 Comment

Does Caravaggio's Style Reflect Nihilism?

10/15/2010

 
Caravaggio painting called David with the Head of Goliath

Nihilism in Art

From time to time I hear some contemporary representational painters being labeled “nihilists". Often this accusation comes from other artists. Painters like Jenny Saville or John Currin are frequent targets.  When one artist is labeling another a “nihilist”, it's usually because the work they make appears in opposition to some value or belief the accuser holds dear.. Frequently the work being called such is not factually nihilistic. It may be exploitative, or ugly, or exploring some ugly or exploitative topic, This does not make it nihilism.

Nihilism is a complex philosophical idea, but the label is often applied in Homer Simpson fashion to suggest that the art in question is in some way a lesser art than the accusers own value system represents. There are many flavors of nihilism; metaphysical nihilism, mereological nihilism, epistemological nihilism, probably even low-fat nihilism. Nietzsche and other philosophers have thought and written about nihilism a great deal. For purposes of this conversation, I’ll use a commonly understood form of nihilism: existential nihilism, which is the essential belief that life has no intrinsic meaning or value. Pessimism, skepticism, hopelessness, despair, recklessness, and rebellion are some traits found in an existential nihilist’s behavior. 

Existential Nihilism has been around a long time, as it reflects a part of the human condition. The darker, brutal, instinctual side of life and its by-products can contribute to nihilistic thinking and behavior. The ancient philosopher Hegesis(c.250 BC) argued that “miseries vastly outnumber pleasures”, so happiness is impossible. Therefore, he advocated suicide. ​Nihilism is not singular to our time or culture, and it is not a product of the 20th Century.

Caravaggio's Tenebrism

​Michelangelo Merisi da Caravaggio(1571-1610) is one of the celebrated artists in the canon of Western painting. He was rewarded and acknowledged in his own lifetime, fell into obscurity, and is today once again recognized for the high art that he produced. Apprenticing first with Simone Peterzano(a student of Titian) and later working in other studios, Caravaggio amplified the practice of Chiaroscuro painting to a level of expression that had profound impact on the Baroque era and many future painters. This extreme chiaroscuro painting is known as Tenebrism.   

A tenebrist painting depicts a strong light, often a 'divine' light emitting from no visible source. Darkness and shadow is the critical foundation of the painting, as it holds and supports the light. Darkness is of at least equal importance to the light. Physically, a viewers vision is always drawn to the light, but the shadow is always present, unnoticed and unconsidered, anchoring the light. Without the dark, the light cannot be held to reveal form or elicit meaning. The fact that Caravaggio understood and expressed this so dramatically through heightening the extremes was not necessarily an isolated painterly device, but perhaps a metaphor for the way he viewed existence. In Tenebrist paintings, the dark takes up more surface area than the light: "miseries vastly outnumber pleasures.”  

Beyond chiaroscuro, if you study Caravaggio’s choices for the depiction of his subject matter you will notice nihilistic tendencies. A cheating cardsharp, worm-holes in his apples, his unique portrayal of the execution of John the Baptist with his own signature in the puddle of blood, and his self-portrayed execution and self-destruction in one version of David and Goliath. These were not usual conventions to include in these works and reflect Caravaggio’s world view. The visual clues are there: skepticism, recklessness, despair, hopelessness. A reality understood from how he lived, with "one foot in the light and one foot in the dark".

In his early years Caravaggio ran the streets of Rome with a group of like-minded individuals who adopted the motto “Nec Spe, Nec Metu” which means “Without hope, without fear.” If there''s a better motto to express existential nihilism, I'm not sure what it is. In Rome, Caravaggio rejected the accepted viewpoint for art as perfect form and ideal beauty. He refused to employ these devices in his works or to convey a vision of divine perfection.

To the dismay and criticism of Classic standard bearer's such as Gian Pietro Bellori, Caravaggio refused to draw sculpture or copy master works. He used models from the street. He portrayed the immediate, the here and now. His self-portrait as "Sick Bacchus" is a clear denial of transcendent beauty and spiritual meaning. Bacchus, the eternal god of pleasure, is depicted by Caravaggio as sickly, dirty, raw, human. Pure visual nihilism. 

Was Caravaggio an existential Nihilist? The label can be applied and might fit more snugly than it fits other painters accused today. If Caravaggio can be labelled a nihilist whose paintings express actual nihilistic qualities, then it follows that magnificent art can indeed be nihilistic. This does not suggest that all nihilism is magnificent art any more than all beauty is magnificent art, but it supports the fact that powerful art is not about transcendence alone.
Basket of Fruit, a still life painting Caravaggio

Could PICASSO “really” paint? YES…he really could, as the evidence shows.

4/11/2010

6 Comments

 
In my early teenage years, I met a classical realist painter at an art show who talked to me about his work. Being a young lover of Baroque painting and wanting to learn to ‘paint like that', I was enthralled, Here was a living expert who could paint ‘real’ stuff. In the 1970’s, you didn't just bump into people like this every day. His paintings whispered to me “here is someone you can learn from.” I fired off countless questions, and he kindly shared his thoughts. At some point I asked him, “Why did Picasso do things like he did and not like this?” He told me, “Oh, don’t worry about Picasso. He couldn't paint. Not really. That’s why he did all that other stuff.”

I’m sure this gentleman meant no harm. He eagerly shared information with me about traditional painting techniques in the short twenty minutes we spoke. The thing is, I didn't remember a word he told me about those ideas. What I did remember and what echoed in my head for years was the thought that “Picasso couldn’t paint.” I wondered why was he was successful and revered by so many people if what I had been told was true. I didn't dwell on it very long, it was easier to accept the notion that “he just couldn't paint.” 
I assumed that must be a fact because an excellent painter who clearly knew a lot more about painting than I did was telling my young mind it was so. Over the years I've encountered this exact same notion expressed in different ways in the world of figurative painting. Old myths die hard.

Later in my career I was discussing art history with a friend who was an art professor. He was a painter, a teacher, an academic, a thinker. His own training had been a product of mid-20th century art education. Many of his thoughts would be anathema to some of today's painters who pursue naturalistic painting.
​
I pushed him on the subject of Picasso. He explained to me what he thought and knew about Picasso. I didn't understand his adoration for Picasso. We argued about it, and in desperation to feel better about my own direction I blurted out, “Yeah, well, Picasso couldn't really paint!” He looked at me, exasperated, but gently said, “Michael, Picasso was a creative genius.” I thought about that for a long time. After all, we are often told to “learn our craft", master the skills and the tools, and then go forth and create. 

I realized then that in order to understand and develop as an artist it would be necessary to not only learn some craft and learn how to expand my creativity, but to also devote time to the study of art history and it's theories. So I put down my palette, crawled out of my dimly lit studio, and started to read.
Imagine my surprise when I stumbled across Picasso’s early paintings, some of which are shown below. Now I don't place these works on the same technical level for design as a Titian or Bouguereau. Consider the first painting(Picasso's portrait of his mother) which was made in 1896. It is technically stronger than many 'realist' painters work of today, and not as strong as others. But weighing the fact that he was fifteen years old when he painted it, I'll forgive him any artistic weakness the painting might hold.

I've often wondered if Picasso had decided to pursue naturalistic figurative painting to his fullest ability, would he have excelled and matured in that particular expression? We'll never know. Pablo Picasso decided to go in other directions and to explore other visual experiences through form. Truly, he was a creative genius, and he left us many treasures.

Could Picasso 'really' paint? My eyes tell me yes. It's a question easily resolved. Perhaps more interesting questions are: Why did he choose other paths? What was he exploring? What did he find? How can I use the knowledge he uncovered for my own pursuit of visual art?


6 Comments
    Picture
    Drunk as a hoot owl,
    writing letters 
    by thunderstorm.
    - Kerouac
     
     

    Musings

    All
    Caravaggio Style
    Cesar Santos Syncretism
    Conundrum Of The Workshops
    Could Picasso Really Draw?
    Petrus Christus Mystery
    Seeing: Molyneaux
    Whistler's Mother: Modern Art
    Why Do We See?
    Winslow Homer Dreams

    connect with michael:

Reach Out
© 2020 MC GUILMET. All Rights Reserved.
  • About
  • PAINTINGS
    • Catskillstyle
    • Fragments 2005-2015
  • Haiku-inspired Poems
  • Aesthetics